|
||||||||||
|
Influence of Arabic and Islamic Philosophy on the
Latin West First published Fri Sep 19, 2008 The Arabic-Latin translation movements in the Middle Ages, which paralleled that from Greek into Latin, led to the transformation of almost all philosophical disciplines in the medieval Latin world. The impact of Arabic philosophers such as al-Fārābī, Avicenna and Averroes on Western philosophy was particularly strong in natural philosophy, psychology and metaphysics, but also extended to logic and ethics. Among the influential Arabic theories are: the logical distinction between first and second intentions; the intension and remission of elementary forms; the soul's faculty of estimation and its object, the intentions; the conjunction between human intellect and separate active intellect; the unicity of the material intellect (Averroism); naturalistic theories of miracles and prophecy; the eternity of the world and the concept of eternal creation; the active intellect as giver of forms; the first cause as necessary existent; the emanation of intelligences from the first cause; the distinction between essence and existence; the theory of primary concepts; the concept of human happiness as resulting from perfect conjunction with the active intellect. 1. Transmission 2. Division of the Sciences 3. Logic 4. Natural Philosophy 4.1 Eternity of the World 4.2 The Elements in a Compound 4.3 Spontaneous Generation 5. Psychology 5.1 Estimation 5.2 Active Intellect 5.3 The Four Intellects 5.4 Averroes' Unicity Thesis 5.5 Naturalistic Theories of Prophecy 6. Metaphysics 6.1 The Subject of Metaphysics 6.2 Primary Concepts 6.3 Essence and Existence, Universals and Individuals 6.4 The First Cause and the Emanation of the Intelligences 7. Ethics Bibliography Other Internet Resources Related Entries -------------------------------------------------------------------------------- 1. Transmission Arabic Philosophy was known in the Latin West through
translations, and, to a small degree, through personal contacts between
Christians and Muslims, as in the case of Frederick II Hohenstaufen, who was
directly acquainted with a number of Muslim scholars. A small number of
Christian scholars, such as Ramón Llull and Ramón Martí, knew Arabic themselves
and drew on Arabic sources when composing Latin works. Translations, however,
were far more influential. The first Arabic-Latin translations to transport
philosophical material into Latin Europe were the translations of texts on
medicine and natural philosophy produced towards the end of the eleventh
century in The translations of philosophical texts proper, such as by al-Kindī, by the anonymous author of the Liber de causis, by al-Fārābī, Isaac Israeli, al-Ghazālī and Avicenna, but also of Greek works transmitted in Arabic, assumed full pace in Toledo in the second half of the twelfth century, where two very prolific translators worked: Dominicus Gundisalvi and Gerard of Cremona. It is likely that al-Fārābī's treatise Enumeration of the Sciences, translated twice, by Gundisalvi and Gerard, served as a model for a coherent translation program. An indication of this is that later Toledan translators such as Alfred of Shareshill, Michael Scot and Hermannus Alemannus filled in gaps in al-Fārābī's list of disciplines which the earlier translators had not covered (Burnett 2001). The translation movement was also influenced by the philosophical preferences of Jewish scholars. Gundisalvi worked together with the Jewish scholar Avendauth when translating Avicenna's De anima, which Avendauth had recommended for translation, and Gundisalvi's other translations may also go back to such recommendations. The impressive Spanish translation movement was motivated and fostered by several factors: the personal interest of individual translators; the demand for scientific texts by the French schools; the availability of Arabic manuscripts in cities newly conquered by the Christians; the patronage of the archbishop of Toledo; and by clerical interests in promoting Latin scientific culture in an Arabic-speaking Christian environment (Hasse 2006). The next important phase of the transmission were the
translations made in Sicily and southern Italy by several translators
associated with the Hohenstaufen or the papal court, the most productive of
which were Michael Scot and William of Luna. It was only about thirty years
after Averroes' death in 1198 that Latin Averroes translations became available
in the newly developing universities (Gauthier 1982b). After about 1300,
Arabic-Latin translation activities ceased, to resume again after 1480. The
Renaissance translations were mostly produced by Italian Jews from Hebrew
versions of Arabic texts, an exception being Andrea Alpago's Avicenna
translations from Arabic (Tamani 1992; Burnett 1999). The social context of
these translations was the vibrant philosophical culture of Italian
universities and especially of The corpus of Arabic philosophical texts translated into Latin was substantial: A recent publication lists 131 textual items (Burnett 2005; see Kischlat 2000, 53–54, 196–198 for the distribution of the translations; on Avicenna translations see Bertolacci, forthcoming). The introduction of Arabic philosophy into Latin Europe led to the transformation of almost all philosophical disciplines. The influence is particularly dominant in natural philosophy, psychology and metaphysics, but is also felt in logic and ethics. (The influence of Jewish philosophers writing in Arabic, such as Ibn Gabirol and Maimonides, is not covered in this article). 2. Division of the Sciences Arabic divisions of the sciences influenced the Latin West mainly through Dominicus Gundisalvi’ treatise Division of Philosophy (De divisione philosophiae). In this text, Gundisalvi reuses much material from his own abbreviating translation of al-Fārābī's Enumeration of the Sciences (Ihsâ’ al-'ulûm), of which a second, more literal translation was produced by Gerard of Cremona. But it was Gundisalvi's own Arabicized treatise which was the main channel of influence. The mostly anonymous introductory literature for artes students of the thirteenth century draws amply on Gundisalvi's treatise, sometimes referring to Gundisalvi as "Alpharabius" (Lafleur 1988, 341n). Gundisalvi adopts central principles for the division of the sciences from Avicenna: that the principal criterion of division between the sciences is their subject matter; that a science cannot demonstrate the existence of its own subject matter; and that there are two kinds of subordination of a science: either as a part (pars) of another science, when it studies a part of its subject matter, or as a species (species) of another science, when it studies the subject matter in a specific respect (Hugonnard-Roche 1984; Fidora/Werner 2007, 24-35). Al-Fārābī's influence is particularly obvious in the enumeration of the seven parts of grammar, the eight parts of natural science (covering the spectrum of Aristotle's libri naturales), and the seven parts of mathematics: arithmetic, music, geometry, optics, astrology, astronomy, the science of weights, the science of technical devices (ingenia) (see the tables in Bouyges 1923, 65–69). As to the discipline of logic, Gundisalvi explicitly embraces al-Fārābī's division into eight parts, following the tradition which makes Aristotle’s Rhetoric and Poetic parts of logic, and he further distinguishes with al-Fārābī between five kinds of syllogistic reasoning, of which demonstration is the highest. The Farabian division of logic into eight parts reappears, for example, in Roger Bacon (Maierù 1987) and in Arnoul de Provence’s Division of the Sciences (ca. 1250); Arnoul remarks that neither Aristotle nor common usage includes Rhetoric and Poetic among the parts of logic (Lafleur 1988, 342). The influence of al-Fārābī's Enumeration of the Sciences extends also to specific areas such as music (Farmer 1934, 31–34). A special case is Michael Scot's Division of philosophy, which adopts substantial material from Gundisalvi, but arranges it according to its own scheme (Burnett 1997). In general, al-Fārābī's and Gundisalvi's works were instrumental in disseminating a systematic division of the sciences which integrated the full range of Aristotle's works and a broad spectrum of sciences, many of which were new to the Latin West (Burnett, forthcoming). 3. Logic The Arabic influence in logic is thinner than in other disciplines (apart from ethics), because only a few works of Arabic logic were translated into Latin. The most influential translations were the Isagoge part of Avicenna's summa The Healing (ash-Shifâ’) and al-Ghazālī’s Intentions of the Philosophers, the first part of which is a reworking of Avicennian logic. Ramon Llull produced an Arabic compendium of al-Ghazālī's text, which he himself translated into Latin (Lohr 1965). To these sources one may add al-Fārābī's Enumeration of the Sciences, which transmitted much material on logical disciplines. Hermannus Alemannus's translation of Averroes' commentary on the Poetics was important because it remained the only source on Aristotelian poetics available in the Middle Ages and had a rich manuscript transmission (for its influence on Petrarch's negative judgement about Arabic poetry see Burnett 1997). Other translated texts remained largely uninfluential, such as William of Luna’s translations of five commentaries by Averroes on Aristotle’s logical works, or the translations made from Hebrew in the Renaissance. In sum, this means that the Latin West was not aware of the more innovative parts of Arabic logic, such as in syllogistics (Street 2005). Of particular influence in scholastic philosophy was Avicenna's theory of the subject matter of logic, with its related doctrine of first and second intentions. Avicenna's basic claim is that logic deals with second-order concepts. This is discussed in the logic part of The Healing, but spelled out in technical vocabulary in the metaphysics part (Metaphysics I,2): "The subject matter of logic is the secondary intelligible concepts (al-ma'anî al-ma'qûla al-thâniyya, intentiones intellectae secundo), which depend on the primary intelligible concepts with respect to the manner by which one arrives through them at the unknown from the known". In this sentence, "concept" (ma'nâ) is rendered in Latin with the term intentio. A brief note on this term is at place: In Arabic-Latin translation literature, intentio is very often used to render ma´nâ, with the consequence that the term intentio took on a similarly broad semantic range as its Arabic counterpart. In the writings of Avicenna, ma'nâ may mean "concept", but also "meaning" of a word, or something "intelligible" by the intellect, or "perceptible" by estimation but not by the external senses (on estimation see section 5.1). In Averroes' epistemology, the term ma'nâ has a specific meaning as the object of memory and a broader meaning as the abstracted content of sensory, imaginative or intelligible forms (Black 1996, 166). In Avicenna's theory of logic, second intentions are defined as the properties of concepts which these concepts acquire when used in attaining knowledge, for example: being a subject or being a predicate, being a premise or being a syllogism. Avicenna thus confirms that logic has a proper subject matter, and hence becomes a full-fledged part of philosophy, and not only a tool for the philosophical disciplines (Sabra 1980, 752–753). Avicenna's definition of logic appears already in Dominicus Gundisalvi (De divisione philosophiae 150). Further Latin writers to adopt Avicenna's thesis that the subject matter of logic is second intentions are Roger Bacon and Thomas Aquinas, followed by many subsequent authors such as Pseudo-Robert Kilwardby, Radulphus Brito, Hervaeus Natalis, Peter Aureoli, Duns Scotus and William of Ockham (Knudsen 1982; Maierù 1987; Perler 1994). It was a matter of dispute how first and second intentions differ, what they refer to and what their ontological status is, a dispute bordering on epistemology and the philosophy of mind. Important participants in this discussion are Roger Bacon, who defines intentions as intelligible species, that is, mental likenesses of things, and Hervaeus Natalis and Peter Aureoli, who (apart from disagreeing on many issues) both hold that intentions are neither identical with extramental things nor with qualities of the intellect; they have their own "intentional being" (esse intentionale), which is the result of a cognitive act (Perler 1994). This position was criticized both by nominalists and realists: William of Ockham objected against the reification of intentions and held that intentions are always natural signs in the mind; second intentions are natural signs which signify other natural signs (Summa logicae I.12); the realist author Walter Burley rejects the idea of a special being of intentions and argues that second intentions are part of extramental reality (Knudsen 1982). Logic as the science of second intentions continued to be a philosophical topic well into the sixteenth century, especially among Thomists and Scotist authors. 4. Natural Philosophy Arabic natural philosophy reached the Latin West earlier than the other philosophical disciplines. The medical and astrological translations of the late eleventh and early twelfth century transported much philosophical material to the Latin world. Under the influence of these Arabic sources, Latin authors of the twelfth century explained natural phenomena by recourse to the four elements, the four qualities, the four humours, the three spiritus (natural, spiritual, animal) and their organs, the localization of the soul’s faculties in different cavities of the brain, the distinction between the sublunar and the heavenly universe, the circular movement of the heavenly spheres, and by using Aristotelian concepts such as matter and form, action and passion, cause and effect. While many Latin writers of the twelfth century continued to understand nature in terms of the Latin Christian tradition, others, such as William of Conches, Adelard of Bath, Hermann of Carinthia and Bernardus Silvestris, drew amply on the new medical and astrological sources, often combining them with the doctrines of Plato's Timaeus (Burnett 1982, introduction). Sometimes they did this by openly dividing their presentation into a section according to the church fathers and a section according to the philosophers and natural scientists (physici), which integrated material from the Latin and Arabic philosophical traditions. The influence of Arabic in natural philosophy in the later Middle Ages, that is, after the translations of Avicenna and Averroes, is particularly strong in psychology (section 5 below). But other disciplines, such as physics, cosmology or zoology, are also influenced by Arabic sources, in particular by Averroes' commentaries. Several theses from Averroes' long commentaries influenced the history of medieval Latin physics: that there is a distinction between motion as an incomplete form and a way towards form; that the place of the heavens is defined with respect to its centre, the earth; that time exists partially in the soul and partially in extramental reality; and that time is an accident that inheres in only one subject, which is the first motion of the heavens (Trifogli 2000; Maier 1955, ch. II.3). One issue on which Avicenna and Averroes disagreed was the "form of bodiliness" (sûra jismiyya, forma corporeitatis), which, Avicenna argued, is the common form of prime matter that underlies all individual bodily forms, whereas Averroes denied that the "form of corporeality" is a form in the category of substance; it is only an accident, to be identified with indeterminate three-dimensionality (Hyman 1965). Thomas Aquinas rejected the idea that prior to the intellective soul there exists a substantial form in matter (Summa theol. Ia q. 76 a. 4, a. 6). The Avicennian concept was adopted by others, such as Henry of Ghent and Duns Scotus, and thus served the theory of the plurality of forms. That prime matter has its own actuality became a principle identifying the Franciscan party in the doctrinal struggles with the Dominicans. The discussion of the concept of forma corporeitatis continued well into the sixteenth century (Des Chene 2000, 81–93). Three prominent topics of natural philosophy are here singled out for closer treatment: the eternity of the world, the persistence of elements in a compound and spontaneous generation. 4.1 Eternity of the World The Greek theory of the eternity of the world was a
challenge to the Christian world view, a challenge increased by the fact that
the theory was supported by Arabic sources: by Avicenna, who combined it with a
metaphysical concept of God as the "necessary being", which is the
eternal efficient cause of the existence of the heavenly and sublunar world
(see section 6.4 on the first cause), and by Averroes, who combined it with a
conception of God as the prime mover established in natural philosophy. In
Giles of Rome’ Errors of the Philosophers, Avicenna and Averroes are accused of
many "errors", but the eternity of the world figures most
prominently. Averroes, in particular, is attacked for opposing "even more
vehemently than did the Philosopher (Aristotle) those who held that the world
had had a beginning" (Giles of Rome 1944, 15). The eternity of the world
and related theses were condemned in In the thirteenth century and beyond, the issue was widely discussed by the scholastics, who arrived at a variety of positions, but unanimously held that the world was created in time by God, which means that they never fully shared Avicenna's or Averroes’ position. Many arguments of the scholastic discussion were drawn from Arabic authorities, from the time of Philip the Chancellor’s Summa de bono onwards (dating 1225–8). Thomas of York, for instance, takes over Averroes' exposition of the four principal views on the issue (Comm. magnum De caelo I.102; Dales 1990, 81). Passages drawn from Arabic texts were not only employed to defend, but also to attack the eternity thesis. One particularly often quoted argument comes from al-Ghazālī's Intentions of the Philosophers: If the world was eternal, an infinite number of (immortal) souls would now exist, which is impossible (Dales 1990, 44, 256). Another very influential source of the Latin debate was Maimonides' Guide for the Perplexed (II.13–28); Maimonides argued that both eternity and non-eternity are possible philosophically. Thomas Aquinas' Commentary on the Sentences (II, d.1 q.1 a.5) is a good example of the impact of Arabic sources. Among the arguments cited from Averroes in favour of eternity are that there is always another moment in time before a moment in time; that only motion can be the cause of a change from rest to motion; that if the world had a beginning, a vacuum would precede the world (Comm. magnum De caelo III.29, Comm. magnum Phys. VIII.8,9,11,15). Avicenna is cited as holding that God's will is unchangeable and never starts anew (an argument drawn also from Averroes), and that it is impossible that God precedes the world in duration, because this implies that time existed before the world and before movement (Metaphysics IX.1). These arguments clearly influenced Thomas' conclusion that the eternity thesis is the most probable in philosophical terms. However, just like creation, eternity escapes full demonstration. From the standpoint of faith, the eternity of the world is false and heretical. In his treatise On the Eternity of the World, Thomas Aquinas, in contrast to most of his contemporaries, defends the possibility of an eternal creation, thus approaching the position of Avicenna and other Neoplatonic thinkers. In the eyes of Siger of Brabant, the natural philosopher cannot but conclude that the world is eternally created, whereas the metaphysician concedes that God's will is inscrutable and that hence there is no certainty about eternity or non-eternity (De aeternitate mundi; Quaest. in tertium De anima q.2). For Boethius of Dacia, the natural philosopher has to infer the eternity of movement from the principles of natural philosophy, but the metaphysician, even though he can demonstrate the existence of a first cause, is unable to demonstrate whether the world is coeternal with the first cause or non-eternal, given the inscrutability of God's will (De aeternitate mundi). Both authors share the conviction that the natural philosopher is forced to conclude that the world is eternal, thus provoking theological opposition. The arguments for this conclusion were largely furnished by Arabic sources. 4.2 The Elements in a Compound In the Latin West, Avicenna and Averroes were known as the principal adversaries on a much-discussed question of element theory, especially in the fourteenth century. Given that all physical substances (apart from the elements themselves) are mixtures of elements, how do the elements exist in them? (Maier 1952; Grant 1974, §77, Eichner 2005, 139–145). Avicenna's answer is that the substantial forms of the elements remain unaltered when a compound is formed; only the qualities of the elements are altered and unite to a mean( quality (qualitas media), or complexion (complexio). The complexion disposes the matter to receive the substantial form of the compound from the active intellect, the giver of forms (dator formarum) (The Healing: Physics I.10, On generation 6). The problem with this position, as the scholastics saw, is that several bodies are combined in one, which do not form a true mixture. Averroes rejects Avicenna's theory and argues that the substantial forms of the elements are diminished in the compound (Comm. magnum De caelo III.67). The form of the compound is "composed" of the elementary forms (Comm. magnum Metaph. XII.22). In order not to violate Aristotle's principle that substantial forms cannot be diminished or augmented (a man is not more man than another), Averroes argued that elementary forms are not substantial forms in the full sense. A third influential alternative was proposed by Thomas Aquinas. Thomas argued that the substantial forms of the elements are destroyed and that only the qualities contribute to the mixture. Thomas shares Avicenna's conviction that every form presupposes a certain material disposition, which is the mean quality characteristic of the compound. But he deviates from Avicenna in that the forms of the elements are not preserved; they are only virtually present in the compound, in that their powers survive (De mixtione elementorum, cf. Summa theol. Ia q. 76 a. 4). Thomas' position found many adherents. Its problem is that physical bodies cannot truly be called mixtures of elements. Avicenna's theory of the permanence of substantial forms was
often mentioned, but rarely accepted in the Latin West. Averroes’ position,
that the elementary forms can be diminished and augmented, found many
supporters, among them Henry of 4.3 Spontaneous Generation Spontaneous generation, that is, the generation of life without their being any parents, as when worms grow in decay, is a much discussed issue of medieval physics and metaphysics. The conflicting explanations of the phenomenon by Avicenna and Averroes much determined the Latin discussion until the sixteenth century. While Avicenna holds that spontaneous generation depends upon ever more refined mixtures of elementary qualities which trigger the emanation of forms from the active intellect, the giver of forms (The Healing: Meteorology II.6), Averroes explains it with the influence of certain celestial constellations which actualize potential forms in water or earth. Avicenna and Averroes also disagree about the special case of the spontaneous generation of human beings, which Avicenna finds possible, whereas Averroes does not. For Averroes, all spontaneously created animals are not true, but abnormal animals (Comm. magnum Metaph. II.15, VII.31, XII.13,18). In the Latin West, Averroes' explanation dominated the discussion for several centuries. Thomas Aquinas argues that there is no need to assume the existence of an Avicennian giver of forms to explain spontaneous generation, since the celestial power suffices for producing ordinary animals from matter. More complex beings, however, such as horses and human beings, cannot be produced by the celestial power alone without the formative power of the semen (Quaest. de potentia, qu. 3 a. 8,9,11). Thomas' position was called the media via by later authors, that is, the middle way between Avicenna and Averroes, since Thomas rejected Avicenna's theory, but also modified Averroes' position in treating spontaneous generation as a natural, and not a miraculous phenomenon. Averroes' theory of celestial influence and Thomas Aquinas' media via became mainstream in the Latin middle ages. A few authors, however, followed Avicenna in allowing for the spontaneous generation of human beings, among them Albertus Magnus, Blasius of Parma, and, in the Renaissance, Pietro Pomponazzi, Paolo Ricci and Tiberio Russiliano (Hasse 2007a). Pomponazzi makes the spontaneous generation of human beings dependent upon the conjunction of the superior planets Jupiter and Saturn, and thus introduces another Arabic theory into the discussion: Albumasar's astrological theory of the great conjunctions (Nardi 1965). A modified version of Avicenna's theory of the giver of forms appears in John Buridan, who deviates from the dominant position that the form of human beings comes from without, i.e. from God, whereas that of animals is educed from matter. Buridan holds that all forms are given by a separate incorporeal substance, which he calls God. The phenomenon of spontaneous generation supports this view, since it cannot be explained with the influence of the stars, which is too weak and imperfect to generate animals (In Metaphysicen Aristotelis lib. 8 q. 9). What does not appear in Buridan, is Avicenna’s theory of the subsequent mixtures of elementary qualities. 5. Psychology In Latin psychology, the influence of Arabic works is particularly strong and lasted well into the sixteenth century. Avicenna and Averroes, the most influential philosophers, presented the West with a faculty psychology in the tradition of Aristotle and enriched by Graeco-Arabic medical doctrines, such as about the cavities of the brain, the nerves, and the spirits which transport information in the body. From about 1220 onwards, the full range of Avicennian faculties (vegetative, external and internal senses, the motive faculties, practical and theoretical intellect) appears in Latin treatises by masters of arts and theologians. This system of faculties remains, by and large, standard for a long time in philosophical handbooks, from the anonymous Philosophy of the Simple (Philosophia pauperum) and Vincent of Beauvais' Mirror of Nature (Speculum naturale) in the thirteenth century up to the Philosophic Pearl (Margarita philosophica) of the 1490s. Averroes disagreed with Avicenna on a number of topics concerning faculty psychology, for example: on the organ and medium of touch (Hasse 2000, 98–106), on the material or immaterial transmission of odors, and on whether human beings have an estimative faculty or not. These controversies were continued in the Latin tradition. The most influential pieces of psychological doctrine imported from the Arabs probably were Avicenna's theory of estimation (wahm), his theory of potential, acquired and active intellects, and Averroes' thesis that there is one intellect for all human beings. 5.1 Estimation Avicenna had argued in his On the Soul (the De anima part of The Healing I.5 and IV.3) that human beings and animals share an internal sense called estimation (wahm, aestimatio), which perceives so-called "intentions" (ma’ânî, intentiones) in an object, such as hostility and friendliness: The sheep perceives hostility in the wolf and judges that the wolf is to be fled from. The basic ingredients of this theory were adopted by many scholastic writers. There was disagreement, however, over several issues: Firstly, Averroes and Thomas Aquinas (in contrast to Avicenna, Albertus Magnus and others) argued that estimation existed in animals only, but not in human beings. To explain instinctive reactions in human beings, it is not necessary, they argue, to assume the existence of a faculty besides the cogitative faculty, or ratio particularis, as Thomas calls it. Secondly, scholastic writers were divided over whether the intentions are perceived in the object, as Avicenna and Thomas Aquinas say, or abstracted from sensory forms, as for instance Albertus Magnus and John Buridan argue (Hasse 2000, 141–153; Black 2000). Thirdly, there was disagreement about the notion of "animal judgement" propagated by Avicenna. Nominalists such as Adam Wodeham argue that judgements always involve the formation of a complex sentence, which presupposes linguistic capabilities; animals, therefore, never truly judge (Perler 2006). 5.2 Active Intellect Typical for Arabic intellect theory is the distinction between several degrees or levels of intellect, from an entirely potential intellect up to a perpetually active intellect, and the assumption, taken over from later Greek philosophers, that the active intellect is an entity separate from the human being. Al-Fārābī, Avicenna and Averroes identify the active intellect with the lowest of the cosmological intelligences, and argue that the human intellect is able to conjoin with the active intellect. The great majority of scholastic writers teach that potential and active intellect are parts of the soul, but there also existed a current adopting the Arabic idea of a separate active intellect (e.g. Dominicus Gundisalvi and Petrus Hispanus). Several scholastic authors identify the active intellect with God on the authority of Avicenna and Augustine – a position which modern scholars have labeled "Augustinisme avicennisant" (Gilson 1926/27, 102). Among the earliest exponents of the doctrine is Jean de la Rochelle; he teaches that the term "active intellect" refers either to God or to the angels' intellect or to the internal light of human beings, depending upon which intellectual objects are grasped by the human intellect (Summa de anima 116). This doctrine reappears in the Summa fratris Alexandri, and in Vincent of Beauvais (Hasse 2000, 220–221). Later adherents are Roger Bacon, John Pecham, Roger Marston, Vital du Four, and also Henry of Ghent (though only in parts of his work). But other scholastics disagree. Adam of Buckfield, Bonaventure and Thomas Aquinas criticize unnamed theologians for identifying the active intellect with God. Thomas rejects the thesis because he interprets it in illuminationist terms and finds it incompatible with his own epistemology of abstraction (Summa contra gentiles II.74). One should note, however, that Avicenna’s epistemology combines both abstractionist and emanationist aspects and that his theory of abstraction also attracted Latin readers (Hasse 2000, 200–203, but cf. also McGinnis 2007). 5.3 The Four Intellects Avicenna distinguishes four different states of the human intellect, which are not different faculties of the soul, but different phases of intellection: three potential intellects, called material, in habitu, in effectu, and one actually thinking intellect, the "acquired intellect" (al-'aql al-mustafâd, intellectus adeptus). The first potential intellect is pure potentiality to know anything; the second potential intellect knows axioms such as "The whole is bigger than the part"; the third has already acquired conclusions through syllogistic reasoning and the intuition of middle terms, but does not consider them at the moment; the "acquired intellect" comes about when the human intellect connects with the active intellect (De anima I.5). This theory exerted a profound influence on scholastic intellect theory, especially in the period from Dominicus Gundisalvi to Albertus Magnus. The scholastics inherited from Avicenna the principal idea that the activity of the human intellect can be differentiated into different phases of gradual development and into different acts of syllogistic reasoning (Hasse 1999 and 2000, 191–200). An important step in the reception of the doctrine is the anonymous treatise De anima et de potentiis eius by a Parisian master of arts of ca. 1225 (Gauthier 1982a, 53). This author adopts from Avicenna the first three levels of intellect, the first being pure potentiality, the second knowing first propositions, the third conclusions, and combines it with teachings from Aristotle's Posterior Analytics (I.3 and II.19) about the intellect knowing axioms and principles. Jean de la Rochelle continues this line and calls the second intellect "intellectus principiorum", the third "intellectus conclusionum", and uses a Boethian term for the axioms of the second intellect: "common notion of the mind" (communis animi conceptio), thus combining the Avicennian doctrine with Western axiomatic theory (Tractatus de divisione multiplici potentiarum animae II.18). In the writings of Albertus Magnus, the influence of Avicenna is combined with that of Averroes, who distinguishes two intellects apart from the separate active intellect: the material intellect, which is pure potentiality (and unique, see section 5.4 below) and the speculative intellect, which is the actuality of the grasped intelligible. Averroes and Avicenna both teach that the human and active intellect conjoin in the moment of intellection. Averroes, in particular, claims that a perfect conjunction with the active intellect resulting in God-like knowledge is possible in this life (Comm. magnum De anima III.5 and III.36). Albertus Magnus, in his early De homine (qu. 56 a. 3), adopts the Avicennian doctrine of three potential intellects in his scholastic reformulation, but in his later works, under the influence of Averroes, transforms it into a theory of intellectual ascension. The highest level of the human intellect is called "acquired intellect" (intellectus adeptus) and results from the conjunction between the potential and the active intellect, both parts of the human soul. In this stage, the intellect is able to grasp all intellectual knowledge, and does not need to have recourse to the senses again. In virtue of this intellect, a human being becomes God-like (De anima 3.3.11). Thomas Aquinas sharply disagrees. The intellect can never dispense with the senses, since it needs the phantasms for conceiving an intellectual form. This is why perfect intellectual knowledge is not possible in this life (Summa theol. Ia q. 84 a. 7). 5.4 Averroes' Unicity Thesis Averroes' thesis that there is only one intellect for all human beings is sometimes labelled "monopsychism", but this is a problematic term, since Averroes' unicity thesis concerns the intellect, not the soul. Averroes' theory has an epistemological and an ontological purpose. On the one hand, Averroes wants to explain how universal intelligibles can be known, on the other hand, he wants to account for Aristotle's claim that the intellect is pure potentiality and unmixed with the body (Comm. magnum De anima III.5). Many scholastic readers were troubled by the problem of whether the material (or potential) intellect, if it is one, can be the form of the body. This problem was not directly addressed by Averroes himself, but by many of his Latin partisans. Modern scholarship is still divided about the beginnings of Averroism, but it seems clear that there existed at least four groups of authors who explicitly adopted the unicity thesis in one of their writings: Siger of Brabant and possibly other masters of arts in later thirteenth-century Paris; a second Parisian group in the early fourteenth century around Thomas Wilton, John of Jandun and John Baconthorpe; several Italian masters of arts at Bologna university in the fourteenth century; and a larger group of authors in Renaissance Italy and especially in Padua. When the medievals used the Latin term averroista, they referred to authors belonging to these groups. The term averroista came into use in the later thirteenth century, but on rare occasions. One of the first appearances is in Thomas Aquinas' treatise On the Unicity of the Intellect (De unitate intellectus). The treatise itself, however, was entitled contra averroistas only in the later manuscript tradition. It was in the decades around the 1500 that the term was used most frequently. Averroistae were associated mainly with the unicity thesis, but also with theories about the eternity of the world, prime matter and happiness (Hasse 2007b, 309–317). Siger of Brabant and John of Jandun were the best known and most influential Averroists. Siger, in his first and most explicitly Averroistic work on the soul, argues that the separate and eternal intellect is united to the body only in an operational union and that the true form of the body is the sensitive soul (Quaest. in tertium de anima, esp. q. 3 and 9). Under the influence of Thomas and others, Siger later revised his position. For John of Jandun, the intellective soul, which in itself is one and separate, operates within the body. It is united to the body only through the assistance of the phantasmata (Brenet 2003). The Renaissance Averroists Agostino Nifo and Luca Prassicio argued that Siger and John of Jandun professed conflicting views: they interpreted Siger as holding that the unique intellect can be united to the body as form and John of Jandun that it cannot. Another influential Averroist was John Baconthorpe: He developed the theory of the so-called "double conjunction" (copulatio bifaria) between intellect and bodily phantasm: one epistemological, one ontological. The ontological conjunction presupposes a union of unique intellect and human being in a way that the intellect becomes a human faculty (Etzwiler 1971, 266–269). Among the most explicit and outspoken Averroists of the Renaissance were Nicoletto Vernia and Luca Prassicio (Hasse 2004). The unicity thesis was attractive philosophically because it explained the possibility of the knowledge of universals and because it took seriously Aristotle's claim that the intellect is pure potentiality and umixed with the body (De anima III.4, 429a22–25). The unicity thesis was included among the doctrines
condemned in 1270 and 1277 in The decades around 1500 saw the high tide of the Averroist current. This found expression also in several doctrinal disputes within the Averroica secta about the correct interpretation of Averroes' standpoint. In the middle of the sixteenth century, with the advent of new trends of Aristotelianism that gave alternative explanation of universal intellection, the unicity thesis lost its appeal. 5.5 Naturalistic Theories of Prophecy The philosophical interpretation of prophecy and miracles is a typical feature of Arabic philosophy. The Latin West was not acquainted with al-Fārābī's concept of the philosopher-prophet, the leader of the excellent city, but with parts of al-Kindī's and Avicenna's theories. The general line of Avicenna's naturalistic theory of prophecy, which describes prophecy as resulting from extraordinary faculties of the soul, was criticized by Thomas Aquinas. Thomas admits that there is also "natural prophecy" which results from the contact of human imagination and intellect with the celestial bodies and angels, but "divine prophecy" is entirely dependent upon God, and not upon the preparedness of the human soul (Quaest. de veritate, q. 12, a. 1 and 3). Among the specifics of prophecy theory, the working of miracles received most attention in the Latin West. al-Kindī's and Avicenna's explanation of miracles is naturalistic in the sense that neither theory involves divine factors. al-Kindī argues in On Rays (De radiis) that if a person conceives a corporeal image in his imagination, the image assumes a material existence in the spiritus that belongs to the faculty. The spiritus in turn sends out rays, which alter objects in the external world (d’Alverny/Hudry 1975, 230–1). An alternative to this extramission theory is formulated by Avicenna, who claims that persons who have perfected their body and soul are able to affect directly the external matter of the world and may produce rain, fertile seasons, and the like – by sheer power of the will. Avicenna arrives at this conclusion by generalizing the principle that there are psychic causes for material effects (De anima IV.4). Albertus Magnus rejects Avicenna's long-distance theory because it breaks with the Aristotelian rule that there is no efficient causation without material contact (De sensu et sensato 1.10). Thomas Aquinas follows a third alternative: that psychic powers can move the intervening medium, and so indirectly act on external objects, which explains the damage caused by an evil eye. Thomas borrows from a passage in Aristotle's On Dreams, in which air is moved and affected by the eyes of menstruating women (459b23–60a24). True miracles, however, are always produced by God (Summa theol. Ia q.117 a. 3). In the later Middle Ages, the Aristotelian theory of the movable medium proved more successful than the extramission and action-at-a-distance theories of al-Kindī and Avicenna. An exception is Roger Bacon, who teaches that some persons are able to send out "powers, forms, and heat" in order to alter bodies outside. Bacon employs al-Kindī's theory of extramission in order to explain magic as a purely natural phenomenon (in De secretis operibus artis et naturae). The high time for Arabic theories of miracles came in the
Renaissance (Hasse 2007c, 121–125). Marsilio Ficino in his Platonic Theology
(Theologia platonica XIII.4.8–9) explains long-distance effects such as the
evil eye with an extramission model reminiscent of al-Kindī: The evil eye
is explained with vapors being emitted from the sorcerer's eyes which reach and
afflict the victim. True miracles, however, cannot be achieved without God's
assistence. Andrea Cattani explicitly adopts Avicenna's theory that noble souls
are able to influence the external world without mediation, but ties this
extraordinary capacity to inspiration by the Holy Ghost. Such reservations do
not appear in Pietro Bairo's adoption of the theory. Pietro Pomponazzi
discusses Avicenna's position, but favours an extramission theory: He explains
a contemporary miracle in the town of 6. Metaphysics The two most important Arabic sources of medieval Latin
metaphysics are the metaphysics part (Ilâhiyyât) of Avicenna's philosophical
summa The Healing (ash-Shifâ’), here referred to as his Metaphysics, because it
presented a completely systematic metaphysics and combined Aristotelian and
Neoplatonic traditions, and Averroes' Long Commentary on the Metaphysics,
because it proved an indispensible tool for understanding Aristotle's text and
offered an alternative to Avicenna's position on several important issues.
Another very influential text was the Discourse on the Pure Good (Kalâm fî mahd
al-khayr, Liber de pura bonitate), known in Latin also as The Book of Causes
(Liber de causis). The anonymous Arabic author of the treatise rearranged
passages from Proclus' Elements of Theology from a monotheistic, creationist
and Plotinian perspective. In 1255, the Latin text became part of the required
curriculum of study in the Faculty of Arts in 6.1 The Subject of Metaphysics It was well known among the scholastics that Avicenna and Averroes disagreed about the subject matter of metaphysics. In the two opening chapters of his Metaphysics, Avicenna argues that no science can demonstrate the existence of its proper subject, and that hence God, whose existence is proven in metaphysics, cannot be its proper subject. The subject (mawdû‘, subiectum) of metaphysics is being as being. What is sought after (matlûb, quaesitum) in metaphysics, is that which unconditionally accompanies being: such as the causes of being, among which God is the first. Averroes countered that the existence of the first principle cannot be demonstrated in metaphysics, since such a proof can only begin with God's effects and with movement in particular. This is why the proof of God belongs to physics. The subject matter of metaphysics is separable beings, among which counts God, as Averroes argues in the Long Commentary on the Physics (ch. I.83, but in other works he assigns this function to being as being; see Bertolacci 2007). Most scholastic authors favoured Avicenna's position over Averroes’s, but within this mainstream position there was disagreement about the manner in which God relates to the subject of metaphysics, being as being. Albertus Magnus defends Avicenna against Averroes' criticism. Being as being is the subject of metaphysics, whereas the divisions and accidents (passiones) of being are what is sought after, among them God and the separate divine beings (Metaph. I.2, Phys. I.3.18). Thomas Aquinas' position is again much influenced by Avicenna: The subject of metaphysics is being as being (or ens commune), whereas God is that which is aimed at in this science, insofar as he is the cause of all being (In Metaph., prooem.). But, other than Avicenna, Thomas argues that God is the proper subject of a different science, the principles of which are given in revelation: theology (Summa theol. Ia q.1). There were three principal positions on the issue in the Latin West (Zimmermann 1998): Albertus and Thomas make God a subject of metaphysics only as cause of the subject; a second group, among them Roger Bacon and Giles of Rome, holds that God is one of several subjects of metaphysics; a third group argue that God is part of the subject of metaphysics. The latter position was influentially formulated by Henry of Ghent (Pickavé 2007), and taken up by many other authors, among them Duns Scotus. Scotus develops his own standpoint against the authorities of Avicenna, Averroes and Henry of Ghent. He agrees with Avicenna that being as being is the subject, but he interprets the notion of being as including all being, be it material or immaterial, thus including God. The notion of being hence assumes a generality that allows for God being included in the subject of metaphysics (Zimmermann 1998, 294–329). 6.2 Primary Concepts In chapter I.5 of his Metaphysics, Avicenna argues that just as there are first and self-evident sentences, there are also fundamental, first known, self-evident concepts, which are common to all beings: the existent, the thing, the necessary. It was due to Avicenna that the primum cognitum, the first object of knowledge became a central topic of medieval Latin metaphysics. The question of the primum cognitum was variously answered. For Guibert of Tournai, Bonaventure and Henry of Ghent, God is the primum cognitum (Goris 1999), for Thomas Aquinas and Duns Scotus being (ens), for Berthold of Moosburg the good (bonum). An example of a primum cognitum theory influenced by Avicenna is Thomas Aquinas’. There cannot be an infinite regress, neither in the order of demonstration, nor in the order of definition, Thomas argues. The first concept is being. It is what is first grasped by the mind, and it is unrestrictedly universal. It is specific for Thomas, however, that the order of definition and of demonstration are not on the same level. The principle of contradiction rests (fundatur) on a conceptual basis, since it can be reduced to the terms out of which it is composed, among which "being" is the first (In Metaph. IV.6; Aertsen 1996, 146–151). Avicenna's theory of primary concepts was an important source for the theory of transcendental concepts, which scholastic philosophers developed in the thirteenth century, taking their cue from Aristotle, Avicenna and the Dionysian tradition (Aertsen 1998). Avicenna bequeathed to the discussion of the transcendentals not only specific teachings about the notions "being", "one" and "thing", but also the general idea that, ontologically, the primary concepts are most common since they are true of everything, and that, epistemologically, they are first known since they are self-evident and not reducable to prior concepts. 6.3 Essence and Existence, Universals and Individuals Among the most influential philosophical doctrines of Arabic origin is the distinction between essence (mâhiyya, essentia) and existence (wujûd, ens), which the Latin West got to know from Avicenna’s Metaphysics, chapters I.5 and V.1–2. The distinction was used by Avicenna in several metaphysical contexts, i.e., in the discussion of primary concepts, of universals and of the first cause. The following presentation focuses on the context of universals. An essence, says Avicenna, exists either in the mind as a universal or outside the mind as a particular. In itself, the concept of an essence is completely independent of the concept of existence, be it as particular or as universal. Universals thus have two components: essence and universality, which is attached to the essence in the mind only. In some of his writings, Avicenna emphasizes that there is universality only if the essence is found in several objects in the external world (Marmura 1979, 49). Thomas Aquinas adopts Avicenna's distinction already in his early On Being and Essence (De ente et essentia IV). Essence can be considered either in itself or with respect to its existence in the soul or in the particular things. Universality and particularity are accidents of essence, which in itself is neither universal nor particular. The universal is a natura communis, which has existence only in the intellect. Individuals are essences individuated by matter with quantitative dimensions, but only at the time of their origin; later individuation is due to the form. In later writings, Thomas develops his concept of essence and existence so that existence is that which actualizes essence (Summa theol. Ia q. 3 a. 4). An influential defender of the real distinction between essence and existence was Giles of Rome. Since he uses the terminology of "thing" (res) for both concepts, he was criticized for turning "existence" into a thing, which itself exists only if another thing "existence" is added, and so on ad infinitum. This argument was voiced against the real distinction by Siger of Brabant and Godfrey of Fontaines (Wippel 1982), but it originally comes from Averroes, who flatly rejects Avicenna's distinction in his Long Commentary on the Metaphysics (IV.3). While some authors take the extreme position that there is only a mental distinction between essence and existence, Henry of Ghent develops a modified version of Avicenna's theory. He distinguishes between essence in itself and as existing, that is, existing in the mind or in the external world. But he attributes a specific kind of existence to the essence in itself (Quodlibet I, 9 and III, 9): esse essentiae ("essential being"), which is the essence's eternal relation to God as its cause. The esse existentiae, in contrast, is the essence's actual existence. Henry thus develops a theory of how essences exist prior to their actual existence in the mind or in the world, enlarging on a brief and tentative reference in Avicenna's Metaphysics I.5 to the "proper existence" (esse proprium) of the essences. Duns Scotus is also inspired by the Avicennian idea that the common nature (natura communis), as Scotus calls it, is neither truly universal nor truly particular in itself and that it is universal only as an object of the intellect. But Scotus' account of individuation differs: The common nature is particular only because of a second "reality" in the object, a principle of individuation or contracting difference, which by later authors was called haecceitas ("thisness"). The distinction between the two "realities" nature and thisness is not real, but formal in the sense that the two are different, but never exist apart from each other (Ordinatio II, d. 3, p. 1, q. 6). The influence of Arabic metaphysics is much more extensive than these brief references to a few well-known thinkers suggest. The influence of Avicenna and Averroes, especially on the subject of metaphysics and on essence and existence, extends to many authors and over many centuries, up to sixteenth-century Jesuit authors such as Benedictus Pereira, Pedro da Fonseca and Francisco Suárez (Leinsle 1985, ch. 2) 6.4 The First Cause and the Emanation of the Intelligences The influence of Avicenna's concept of the first cause as the only necessary being (wâjib al-wûjûd, necesse esse) and of his theory of emanation is apparent already in the twelfth century. Dominicus Gundisalvi, the Avicenna translator, distinguishes in his Procession of the World (De processione mundi) between the first cause, which is the "necessary being" (necesse esse), and the created beings, which in themselves are only possible existents. The entire universe proceeds from the first cause. The principles first created, however, are not the intelligences, as in Avicenna's metaphysics, but the material and formal principles of the things (Jolivet 1988, 138–140). The anonymous author of The Book of First and Second Causes (Liber de causis primis et secundis), which dates from the turn of the thirteenth century, does not adopt the distinction between necessary and possible beings, but describes the process of emanation in strongly Avicennian terms: From the first cause issues a first created being, an intellect. From this intellect, in turn, emanates a series of intelligences, the lowest of which is the active intellect. Emanation happens in triads: From an intelligence emanates, in virtue of its intellectual activity, the form of a celestial sphere, the body of a sphere, and another intelligence (ch. 4). The anonymous author also draws on the Book of Causes (see the beginning of section 6 above), for instance when describing the hierarchy of intelligences as a decrease in power and unity (ch. 6). William of Auvergne is much attracted by Arabic metaphysical and pyschological theories (which he often indiscriminately attributes to "Aristotle and his followers") and discusses them at length, but often rejects them in the end as conflicting with Christian faith. In On the Universe (De universo II.1), William discusses and rejects the Avicennian emanation system: the necessity of causation through the first cause; the emanation of the intelligences from the first intelligence down to the active intellect; the active intellect as the efficient cause of human souls. He nevertheless tacitly adopts the metaphysical principle "From one arises only one" (de uno non nisi unum) from Avicenna (Teske 1993) and describes the first cause as the "being necessary through itself" (Teske 2002). Thomas Aquinas adopts from Avicenna the description of God as the necessary being, whose essence is its own existence (Summa contra gentiles I.22). The third of Thomas' five proofs for the existence of God in the Summa theologiae (Ia q. 2 a. 3) advances via "the possible and the necessary": It establishes the existence of something necessary in virtue of itself. The proof is much coloured by Avicennian metaphysics, but its direct source is Maimonides' Guide for the Perplexed (II.1), from which it deviates only in minor respects. A conspicuous element of Maimonides' and Thomas' proof is the premise, not explicitly formulated by Avicenna, that every possibility is eventually realized, which is a version of the principle of plenitude (Davidson 1987, 378–388). Thomas, however, rejects the Avicennian theory of emanation. The creation of the world is not a necessary process, and it does not occur through intermediaries, that is, intelligences or angels. He also rejects Avicenna's concept of a separate active intellect as the giver of the forms of the sublunar world and as the ontological place of the intelligibles (Summa contra gentiles II.42 and II.76). The attraction of Avicenna's position is evident in the work of Siger of Brabant. In some of his writings, Siger teaches that God as the first being creates only one being immediately, the first immaterial substance, from which emanate the other intelligences, the celestial spheres and finally the sublunar world, in an eternal and necessary process. The necessity is not universal, however, but finds its limits in the contingency and in the free will which exists in the sublunar world (De necessitate et contingentia causarum; Van Steenberghen 1991, 346). Duns Scotus, in contrast, is very critical of Avicenna's theory of necessary causation through the first cause. He advances several reasons against it, the most important being that there can only be contingency in the world if the first cause does not act by necessity (Ordinatio I d. 8 p. 2 q. un). Several theses on the first cause and the intelligences which are inspired by Avicenna are condemned by the Parisian bishop in 1277, among them: that God is the first necessary cause of the first intelligence and of the celestial movements (art. 58 and 59), that God does necessarily what is immediately produced by him (art. 53), that the active intellect is a substance separate from the human intellect (art. 123), that the rational souls are created by the intelligences (art. 30). Avicenna's theory of the first cause nevertheless continued to influence the scholastic discussion. This is true, for instance, of the proof for the existence of God. Peter of Auvergne, Henry of Ghent and Duns Scotus all draw on Avicenna's argument from the possible and necessary being (Druart 2002; Janssens 2003; Pickavé 2007, ch. 6). The 1270 and 1277 condemnations were also directed against another theory dependent upon Arabic sources: astrological determinism (art. 143, 161, 167, 195, 206, 207), as were previous attacks upon philosophy, such as Bonaventure's Collationes. Since Avicenna was critical of astrology and since Averroes embedded astrological doctrines in Peripatetic mainstream theories about the influence of the stars, the condemnations do not testify to the influence of Arabic philosophers proper, but to that of Arabic astrological authorities such as Albumasar and Alcabitius. 7. Ethics The influence of Arabic ethical and political writings is thin, partly because Arabic philosophers were less productive in these fields, and partly because important works were not translated at all (such as al-Fārābī's Principles of the Citizens of the Perfect State) or as late as in the sixteenth century (such as Averroes' Commentary on Plato’s Republic). Nevertheless, Arabic philosophers exerted an important influence on the discussion of human happiness via their teaching on the intellect. Al-Fārābī, Avicenna and Averroes share the view that happiness is reached through the conjunction of the human intellect with the separate active intellect. They also share an epistemological optimism that for specifically gifted people, which they described as philosophers or philosopher-prophets, a perfect conjunction is possible in this life. Albertus Magnus's theory of happiness is much influenced by these Arabic theories. As was mentioned above, he adopted the concept of an "acquired intellect" (intellectus adeptus) as the highest level of conjunction between possible and active intellect. Only in this stage, a human being truly becomes a human being. Through the conjunction with the active intellect the human intellect contemplates the separate substances, and in this consists the "theoretical happiness" of man (felicitas contemplativa), a happiness which is possible in this life (De anima III.3.12) (Müller 2006). Thomas Aquinas disagrees with the epistemological premisses and the ethical conclusion: Since human knowledge is bound to the senses, knowledge of the immaterial substances is not possible in this life, and neither is perfect human happiness (Summa theol. Ia IIae q. 3 a. 2). In 1277, several philosophical theses concerning human
happiness and the good life were condemned: that happiness is to be had in this
life and not in another (art. 176), that there is no better state (of life)
than studying philosophy (art. 40). These articles are apparently directed at
masters of arts at the Bibliography Aertsen, J. A. (1996), Medieval Philosophy and the
Transcendentals: the Case of Thomas Aquinas, Aertsen, J. A. (1998), "What is First and Most
Fundamental? The Beginnings of Transcendental Philosophy", in Was ist
Philosophie im Mittelalter?, in J. A. Aertsen and A. Speer, eds, Bertolacci, A. (2007), "Avicenna and Averroes on the Proof of God's Existence and the Subject-Matter of Metaphysics", Medioevo, 32: 61–97. Bertolacci, A. (forthcoming), "Community of
Translators: The Latin Medieval Versions of Avicenna's Kitāb
al-Shifā’ (Book of the Cure)", in J.N. Crossley and C.J. Mews, eds,
Communities of Learning: Networks and the Shaping of Intellectual Identity in Black, D. L. (1996), "Memory, Individuals, and the Past in Averroes' Psychology", Medieval Philosophy and Theology, 5: 161–187. Black, D. L. (2000), "Imagination and Estimation: Arabic Paradigms and Western Transformations", Topoi, 19: 59–75. Bouyges, M. (1923), "VII. Sur le De scientiis d'Alfarabi, récemment édité en arabe à Saida et sur le de Divisione Philosophiae de Gundissalinus", Mélanges de l’Université Saint-Joseph de Beyrouth, 9: 49-70. Brenet, J.-B. (2003), Transferts du sujet: la noétique
d'Averroès selon Jean de Jandun, Burnett, C. (1982), Hermann of Carinthia, De essentiis,
critical edition, translation and commentary, Burnett, C. (1997a), "Vincent of Beauvais, Michael Scot and the ‘New Aristotle’", in S. Lusignan and M. Paulmier–Foucart, eds, Vincent de Beauvais, frère prêcheur: un intellectuel et son milieu au XIIIe siècle, Grâne: Editions Créaphis, 189–213. Burnett, C. (1997b), "Petrarch and Averroes: An Episode
in the History of Poetics", in I. Macpherson and R. Penny, eds, The
Medieval Mind: Hispanic Studies in Honour of Alan Deyermond, Burnett, C. (1999), "The Second Revelation of Arabic
Philosophy and Science: 1492–1575", in C. Burnett and A. Contadini, eds,
Islam and the Italian Renaissance, Burnett, C. (2001), "The Coherence of the Arabic-Latin
Translation Program in Burnett, C. (2005), "Arabic into Latin: the reception of Arabic philosophy into Western Europe", in P. Adamson and R.C. Taylor, eds, The Cambridge Companion to Arabic Philosophy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 370–404. Burnett, C. (forthcoming), The Place of Magical and Alchemical Works in the Arabic-(Castilian)-Latin Translation Movement of the 12th-13th Centuries: Two Approaches to Natural Science in the Twelfth Century, in: proceedings of the 2007 Frankfurt am Main conference "Christlicher Norden – Muslimischer Süden", organized by R. Berndt, M. M. Tischler and A. Fidora. Daiber, H. (1990), "Lateinische Übersetzungen
arabischer Texte zur Philosophie und ihre Bedeutung für die Scholastik des
Mittelalters. Stand und Aufgaben der Forschung", in J. Hamesse and M.
Fattori, eds, Rencontres de cultures dans la philosophie médiévale: traductions
et traducteurs de l’antiquité tradive au XIVe siècle, Louvain-la-Neuve:
Université catholique de Louvain; Dales, R. C. (1990), Medieval discussions of the eternity of
the world, Davidson, H. A. (1987), Proofs for eternity, creation, and
the existence of God in medieval Islamic and Jewish philosophy, d’Alverny, M.-Th. / Hudry, F. (1975), "Al-Kindi: De radiis", Archives d'histoire doctrinale et littéraire du Moyen Âge, 41: 139–260. d'Ancona Costa, C. (1995), Recherches sur le Liber de
causis, Des Chene, D. (2000), Life's form: late Aristotelian
conceptions of the soul, Druart, Th.-A. (2002), "Avicenna's Influence on Duns
Scotus' Proof for the Existence of God in the Lectura", in J. Janssens and
D. De Smet, eds, Avicenna and HisHeritage, Eichner, H. (2005), Averroes: Talkhīs kitāb
al-kawn wa-al-fasād. Mittlerer Kommentar zu Aristoteles' De generatione et
corruptione, Etzwiler, J. P. (1971), "Baconthorp and the Latin Averroism: The Doctrine of the Unique Intellect", Carmelus, 19: 235–292. Farmer, H. G. (1934), Al-Fārābī’s
Arabic-Latin Writings on Music, Fidora, A. / Niederberger, A. (2001), Von Bagdad nach Fidora, A. / Werner, D. (2007), Dominicus Gundissalinus: De divisione philosophiae: Lateinisch/Deutsch, Über die Einteilung der Philosophie, Freiburg im Breisgau: Herder. Gauthier, R.-A. (1982a), "Le Traité De anima et de potenciis eius d’un maître ès arts (vers 1225)", Revue des Sciences philosophiques et théologiques, 66: 27–55. Gauthier, R.-A. (1982b), "Notes sur les débuts (1225-1240) du premier ‘Averroisme’", Revue des Sciences philosophiques et théologiques, 66: 321–374. Giles of Rome (1944), Errores philosophorum: critical text
with notes and introduction by Josef Koch … English translation by John O.
Riedl, Gilson, E. (1926/27), "Pourquoi Goris, W. (1999), "Die Anfänge der Auseinandersetzung um das Ersterkannte im 13. Jahrhundert: Guibert von Tournai, Bonaventura und Thomas von Aquin", Documenti e studi sulla tradizione filosofica medievale, 10: 355–369. Grant, E. (1974), A Source Book in Medieval Science, Hasse, D. N. (1999), "Das Lehrstück von den vier Intellekten in der Scholastik: von den arabischen Quellen bis zu Albertus Magnus", Recherches de Théologie et Philosophie médiévales, 66: 21–77. Hasse, D. N. (2000), Avicenna's De Anima in the Latin West:
The Formation of a Peripatetic Philosophy of the Soul, 1160–1300, Hasse, D. N. (2004), "The Attraction of Averroism in the Renaissance: Vernia, Achillini, Prassicio", in P. Adamson, H. Baltussen, M. W. F. Stone, eds, Philosophy, Science and Exegesis in Greek, Arabic and Latin Commentaries, 2 vols., London: Institute of Classical Studies, vol. 2, 131–147. Hasse, D. N. (2006), "The Social Conditions of the Arabic-(Hebrew-)Latin Translation Movements in Medieval Spain and in the Renaissance", in A. Speer and L. Wegener, eds, Wissen über Grenzen: Arabisches Wissen und lateinisches Mittelalter, Berlin: de Gruyter, 68–86 and 806. Hasse, D. N. (2007a), "Spontaneous Generation and the
Ontology of Forms in Greek, Arabic, and Medieval Latin Sources", in P.
Adamson, ed., Classical Arabic Philosophy: Sources and Reception, Hasse, D. N. (2007b), "Averroica secta: Notes on the Formation of Averroist Movements in Fourteenth-Century Bologna and Renaissance Italy", in J.-B. Brenet, ed., Averroes et les Averroïsmes juif et latin, Turnhout: Brepols, 307–331. Hasse, D. N. (2007c), "Arabic philosophy and
Averroism", in J. Hankins, ed., Cambridge Companion to Renaissance
Philosophy, Hugonnard-Roche, H. (1984), "La classification des sciences de Gundissalinus et l’influence d’Avicenne", in J. Jolivet and R. Rashed, eds, Etudes sur Avicenne, Paris: Belles Lettres, 41–75. Hyman, A. (1965), "Aristotle's ‘First Matter’ and
Avicenna's and Averroes' ‘Corporeal Form’", in Harry Austryn Wolfson
Jubilee Volume, 3 vols, Janssens, J. (2003), "Elements of Avicennian Metaphysics in the Summa", in G. Guldentops and C. Steel, eds, Henry of Ghent and the Transformation of Scholastic Thought, Leuven: Leuven University Press, 41–59. Jolivet, J. (1988), "The Arabic Inheritance", in
P. Dronke, ed., A History of Twelfth Century Western Philosophy, Kischlat, H. (2000), Studien zur Verbreitung von Übersetzungen arabischer philosophischer Werke in Westeuropa 1150–1400: Das Zeugnis der Bibliotheken, Münster: Aschendorff. Knudsen, C. (1982), "Intentions and Impositions", in N. Kretzmann, A. Kenny, J. Pinborg, eds, The Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 479–495. Lafleur, C. (1988), Quatre introductions à la philosophie au
XIIIe siècle. Textes critiques et études historique, Leinsle, U. G. (1985), Das Ding und die Methode: methodische
Konstitution und Gegenstand der frühen protestantischen Metaphysik, Lemay, R. J. (1962), Abu Ma'shar and Latin Aristotelianism
in the twelfth century: the recovery of Aristotle's natural philosophy through
Arabic astrology, Lohr, C.H. (1965), "Logica Algazelis: Introduction and Critical Text", Traditio, 21: 223–290. Maier, A. (1952), An der Grenze von Scholastik und
Naturwissenschaft: Studien zur Naturphilosophie des 14. Jahrhunderts, 2. ed., Maier, A. (1955), Metaphysische Hintergründe der
spätscholastischen Naturphilosophie, Maierù, A. (1987), "Influenze arabe e discussioni sulla
natura della logica presso i latini fra XIII e XIV secolo", in B. Scarcia
Amoretti, ed., La diffusione delle science islamiche nel Medio Evo europeo, Marmura, M. E. (1979), "Avicenna's Chapter on
Universals in the Isagoge of his Shifa", in A. T. Welch and P. Cachia,
eds, Islam: Past influence and present challenge, McGinnis, J. (2007), "Making Abstraction Less Abstract:
The Logical, Psychological, and Metaphysical Dimensions of Avicenna's Theory of
Abstraction", in M. Baur, ed., Intelligence and the Philosophy of Mind, Müller, J. (2006), "Der Einfluß der arabischen
Intellektspekulation auf die Ethik des Albertus Magnus", in A. Speer and
L. Wegener, ed., Wissen über Grenzen: Arabisches Wissen und lateinisches Nardi, B. (1965), "Pietro Pomponazzi e la teoria di
Avicenna intorno alla generazione spontanea nell’uomo", in B. Nardi, Studi
su Pietro Pomponazzi, Perler, D. (1994), "Peter Aureol vs. Hervaeus Natalis on Intentionality, A Text Edition with Introductory Remarks", Archives d’Histoire Doctrinale et Littéraire du Moyen Age, 61: 227–262. Perler, D. (2006), "Intentionality and Action: Medieval Discussions on the Cognitive Capacities of Animals", in M.C. Pacheco and J.F. Meirinhos, eds, Intellect et imagination dans la philosophie médiévale, 3 vols, Turnhout: Brepols, vol. 1, 73–98. Pickavé, M. (2007), Heinrich von Gent über Metaphysik als
erste Wissenschaft: Studien zu einem Metaphysikentwurf aus dem letzten Viertel
des 13. Jahrhunderts, Sabra, A. I. (1980), "Avicenna on the Subject Matter of Logic", The Journal of Philosophy, 77: 746–764. Steel, C. (2001), "Siger of Brabant versus Thomas Aquinas
on the Possibility of Knowing the Separate Substances", in J. A. Aertsen,
K. Emery, Jr., A. Speer, eds, Nach der Verurteilung von 1277: Philosophie und
Theologie an der Universität von Paris im letzten Viertel des 13. Street, T. (2005), "Logic", in P. Adamson and R.C. Taylor, eds, The Cambridge Companion to Arabic Philosophy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 247–265. Tamani, G. (1992), "Traduzioni ebraico-latine di opere
filosofiche e scientifiche", in I. Zinguer ed., L’hébreu au temps de la
Renaissance, Teske, R. J. (1993), "William of Teske, R. J. (2002), "William of Auvergne's Debt to Avicenna", in J. Janssens and D. De Smet, eds, Avicenna and His Heritage, Leuven: Leuven University Press, 153–170. Trifogli, C. (2000), Van Steenberghen, F. (1991), La philosophie au XIIIe siècle, Louvain-la-Neuve: Institut supérieur de philosophie. Wippel, J. F. (1982), "Essence and Existence", in N. Kretzmann, A. Kenny, J. Pinborg, eds, The Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 385–410. Zimmermann, A. (1998), Ontologie oder Metaphysik? Die
Diskussion über den Gegenstand der Metaphysik im 13. und 14. Jahrhundert; Texte
und Untersuchungen, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/arabic-islamic-influence/ |
Please report any
broken links to
Webmaster
Copyright © 1988-2012 irfi.org. All Rights Reserved.
Disclaimer