|
||||||||||
|
Who
Needs An Islamic State? By
Yoginder Sikand 15 July, 2009 Countercurrents.org Abdelwahab El-Affendi is a well-known Islamic
scholar and political philosopher from Sudan, presently based in London. Author
of numerous works, his latest book, provocatively titled ‘Who Needs an Islamic
State?’ discusses what he regards as the serious lacunae in contemporary
Islamist political thought, which, in his view, have caused Islamist movements
to reach a virtual dead-end, creating many more problems (for Muslims as well
as others) than they have been able to solve. El-Affendi seeks to argue the
case for a paradigm shift in Muslim political thinking in order to fashion a
contextually relevant understanding of Islam and its role in, and relation to,
the public sphere. Islamism may be described as a version of Islam
predicated on the centrality of the notion of an ‘Islamic state’ whose
principal function is to enforce, and rule by, what is conventionally regarded
as shariah law. Islamism is far from being the homogenous phenomenon that it is
often taken to be. Nor are all versions of Islamism necessarily incompatible
with democracy. Undeniably, however, many forms of Islamism are. Islamist
ideologues, driven by triumphalist, even apocalyptic, fervor, have failed to a develop
consistent position on such crucial issues as limits to state authority,
people’s participation in law-making and governance, the role and status of
non-Muslims and women and the question of violence. Almost all recent
experiments in setting up ‘Islamic states’ have involved tremendous bloodshed,
conflict and large-scale suppression of democratic rights, including of Muslims
themselves. The tantalizing utopian society that Islamists promise to usher in
seems to recede even further into the realm of possibility once Islamists come
to power. This, in brief is what El-Affendi argues in his
book. He contends that, once in power, Islamist parties inevitably turn sternly
authoritarian. This is inevitable, he suggests, because the leaders of these
parties firmly believe that their understanding of Islam corresponds most
closely to the Divine Will and hence cannot be opposed and must be imposed,
even against the opposition of a significant section of the population, Muslims
as well as others. Islamists in power generally have a very poor record of
respecting democracy, though the author rightly notes, it is unfair to blame
them alone for the serious democratic deficit in much of the Muslim world since
they are more often than not the victims of despotism, both of Western
imperialist powers and of regimes in Muslim counties closely allied to the
West. Yet, he insists, even victims have choices. When out of power, the
‘misguided anti-democratic rhetoric’ of Islamists provides many a despot with
‘an alibi and a pretext to oppose democratisation’, and in the few instances
when Islamists have managed to acquire power, their record in upholding
democratic rights has generally been dismal. El-Affendi critiques the Islamists obsession with
the struggle for acquiring power as a means to enforce shariah. Instead, he
advises that it is not primarily political but, rather, moral influence that
Islam requires its followers to seek to acquire. The best way to communicate
Islam to others, which is the principal duty of Muslims, is not through the
force of arms, but, rather, for Muslims to exemplify Islamic virtues in their
own lives and to offer an alternative model of life to the rampant consumerism
and centralization of power characteristic of Western-inspired models of ‘modernity’.
Sadly, he says, this is not happening. In fact, or so he claims, Muslims are
even more materialistic than others, while contributing little or nothing to
the world in terms of science and technology. As he very aptly, though bluntly,
puts it, ‘We sound a lot sillier today when we claim that the Muslims should be
a light unto mankind and show exemplary conduct and moral leadership. Now, it
would be more realistic to just say we wish that Muslims should stop blowing
themselves up and getting innocent people killed in the process.’ El-Affendi recognizes continued injustices directed
by others against Muslims, as in Palestine, Afghanistan and Iraq, and also
admits that violence in the name of Islam is often a response or reaction to
the oppression of Western powers and of their client regimes in the Muslim
world. Yet, he suggests, reacting to this with indiscriminate counter-violence,
as some Islamist groups have, is not in line with Quranic teachings. Further,
he adds, ‘The quest for the moral high ground is for Muslims not just a
requirement of a higher moral order but an imperative of survival.’ El-Affendi believes that values underlying
democracy, such as justice, fairness, decency, rational conduct, can be said to
be ‘total harmony’ with a certain broad and inclusive understanding of Islam.
The anti-democratic thrust of much contemporary Islamic political thought is
thus not a necessary outcome of Islam itself. Rather, the he argues, it owes
much to the fact that Islamism emerged as a response to Western colonialism and
the collapse of the Ottoman Caliphate at the hands of Western powers. That
historical context in which it emerged favored an authoritarian vision of
state. Yet, El-Affendi says, that model of the state is outdated and does not
do justice to the demands of Islam, for it miserably fails to guarantee justice
and basic freedoms that, in his view, Islam insists upon. At the same time, he
is not unmindful of the present imbalance of power at the global level that is
heavily tilted against Muslim countries. One way to address the problem, he
suggests, is for at least one leading Muslim state to be set up or promoted
that would be accepted by other Muslim countries as a sort of leader, in the
same manner in which the USA is accepted as the leader of the West. This would
be less ambitious than the classical Muslim Caliphate, and would fall short of
leading to a European Union sort of arrangement, though it could eventually
lead to it. Such a state, which should be a viable democracy with a strong economic
base and vibrant cultural life, could, he believes, play a major role in
addressing the endemic instability of the Muslim world. He holds this out as a
realistic alternative to the utopian vision of the Caliphate in Islamist
circles. A major concern of El-Affendi is to critique certain
key aspects of traditional and contemporary Muslim political thought and
discourse. He laments that many Muslims are reluctant to review the Muslim
political heritage, somehow treating it as sacred, and even ardently defending
those aspects of it that are patently immoral and, therefore, un-Islamic. For
Muslims to critically reassess this heritage, he points out, does not mean
abandoning the absolute commitment to the ideals that shaped it. A major aspect
of Muslim political thought that he subjects to incisive critique is what he
regards as its extreme idealism and the related tension between the ideal and
the reality of Muslim political life. Islamists, he argues, are impelled by an
extremely idealistic, indeed utopian, vision of the world, one that has scant
concern for realism. Hence their willingness to resort to violence and
authoritarianism to serve what they believe are divine ends. Hence, too, their
ultimate failures. Commitment to Islamic ideals must go, El-Affendi advises,
with what he calls a ‘healthy realism’. While defending democracy and the rights of
minorities, El-Affendi does not advocate that Muslim countries uncritically
adopt Western-style secular, democratic state structures. In fact, he is
bitterly critical of the modern state, which, instead of serving society,
demands that society serve it. He draws inspiration from the polity set up by
the Prophet Muhammad, which was, he says, characterized by voluntary
participation, and was based on morality rather than coercion. The ideal polity established by the Prophet was,
however, subverted shortly after the Prophet’s demise, when the
proto-democratic Caliphate was transformed into authoritarian monarchy that
heralded the collapse of the idealist project. This, El-Affendi notes, resulted
in the decline of the role of the wider community in political affairs and the
further narrowing of Muslim political theory. It was at this time that
doctrines were invented, including by some court-related ulema, making obedience
to rulers compulsory even if they were tyrants. This justification that was
sought to be bestowed on tyranny remains a greatly problematic aspect of Muslim
political thought. Another major drawback of traditional Muslim and
modern Islamist political theory is, El-Affendi tells us, that since it is
based on the notion of the Caliph as a virtually saintly leader, there are no
proper checks and balances to his powers. The insistence on perfection in the
Caliph, he perceptively notes, ‘has automatically removed from the community
the right to criticize him, for everyone is by definition less pious, less
learned and less wise than he is.’ The solution to the problems of the Muslim
ummah was believed to depend on the arrival of an individual saintly ruler, which
is precisely what leaders of various Islamist groups and Muslim messianic
movements projected themselves as. The waiting for this ‘impossible arrival’
was, El-Affendi comments, ‘bound to relegate Muslim thinking to the realm of
mythology and passive ineptitude.’ He suggests that Muslim political theory be
revised by detailing the ideals inherent in Islamic history and norms in a more
realistic fashion, and by insisting that they be adhered to in practice. El-Affendi is bitterly critical of the tendency in
Islamist circles to project the Caliphate as an end in itself, rather than as a
means to certain desirable ends, such as justice and democracy. He finds fault
with key Islamist ideologues, such as Maududi and Syed Qutb, for their aversion
to democracy and their advocacy of a totalitarian, fascist-like state in the
name of the Caliphate, whose ruler would be advised by a shura council but who
could override its opinion. This would allow him to be a virtual dictator. In
such a set-up, El-Affendi argues, totalitarianism would be further reinforced
because the Caliph and the state he presides over would be charged with the
responsibility of promoting virtue and combating vice, which could easily
result in malpractices as well as gross interference in people’s private
affairs. This, in turn, would surely lead to people opposing the Islamic state,
as the experience of numerous countries where such experiments have been sought
to be imposed so tragically illustrates. In this regard, El-Affendi argues for effective
checks on the powers of the Caliph or amir or leader of the Muslim state,
because, he says, the conventional notion that the Caliph cannot be a tyrant
because only the most pious persona can be selected for the post is wholly
unrealistic. He notes that some scholars suggest that the amir be bound by the
consensus (ijma) of the ulema, but he prefers to concur with the suggestion of
Hasan al-Turabi, head of the Sudanese Muslim Brotherhood, who argues that the
amir should follow the ijma of the people, whose choice should be enlightened
by religious as well as secular experts. El-Affendi also approvingly refers to
the noted Tunisian Islamist Rashid al-Ghanoushi, who stresses that Islamist
movements should consider themselves as just one among many actors within a
liberal-democratic state and that they should regards themselves neither as the
guardians of Islamic morality, nor as the sole authority as regards the
interpretation of Islam. In other words, an Islamist party must shed its
monopolistic tendencies and see itself as just another political party offering
its programme to people, inviting them to decide freely between it and its
rivals. In such a scheme of things, Islamic parties must acknowledge that there
is always a possibility that they could lose to non-Islamic parties in
freely-held elections, and they should respect the verdict of the electorate. Another key aspect of Islamist political thought
that El-Affendi scrutinizes is its vision of the state that is based on the
notion of what he aptly terms ‘a principle of restriction’, which he contrasts
with the original Islamic vision of the polity as based on ‘a principle of
liberation and self-fulfillment’. This model is based on the notion of a
benevolent autocrat who rules mainly though punitive powers. Not surprisingly,
this model has throughout Muslim history been used by despots to shore up their
own legitimacy and powers. Another crucial flaw of this model is what he terms
as the ‘totalitarian quasi-utopian vision in which the Islamists conceive of a
mighty state dragging an unwilling community along the path of virtue and
obedience to the law’. This is reflected in their concern mainly with legal
prohibitions and restrictions in the law. The citizen that Islamists seek to
mould is essentially someone who is deprived of the freedom to sin, but,
ironically, also one who lacks the freedom to be virtuous either. El-Affendi
argues that this was certainly not God’s purpose when He created human beings
endowed with free will. The issue of community identity in an Islamic state
also remains a subject of intense debate, El-Affendi points out. While many
Islamists insist on following the medieval fiqh tradition in treating
non-Muslims as dhimmis, with several restrictions on their rights, he refers to
some Islamist ideologues who are now willing to revise the notion of dhimmi and
consider non-Muslims as co-founders of the state and as full citizens with
equal rights as Muslims. This reflects a growing realization that the division
of the world in the classical fiqh tradition between dar ul-harb (‘Abode of
War’) and dar ul-islam (‘Abode of Islam’) is a post-Quranic development that
has no sanction in the Quran. El-Affendi eagerly supports the notion of dar
ul-ahd (‘Abode of Treaty’) that some Muslim scholars have proposed, connoting
states where communities agree to peacefully coexist. In such states,
democracies where Muslims have equal rights, including the right to follow and
propagate their faith, there can be no room for armed jihad, and Muslims must
seek to cultivate peaceful and harmonious relations with non-Muslim fellow
citizens. This, however, does not mean, El-Affendi clarifies,
that Islam is reconciled to the present Western-inspired international order,
for, he says, it must play its role of being the sole remaining major
challenger to the liberal-democratic Western-dominated international system in
order to establish justice, first within Muslim communities and countries, and
then, internationally. Similarly, with reference to the notion of ummah, which
some radical Islamists argue must translate into political unity of all Muslims
across the world, El-Affendi chooses to side with those Muslim thinkers who
consider that the notion does not preclude allegiance to a particular state.
True, he argues, a Muslim’s ultimate loyalty must be to God, not to a community
or state. Yet, other loyalties, such as to the family, tribe, nation and
country, need not be seen as necessarily contradictory to this ultimate
loyalty. This is why, he says, Islam recognized these other facets of identity,
but sublimated and gave them a new expression within the new context of belief.
In some ways, he adds, modernity and the modern system of nation- states can
actually help advance some Islamic ideals. In theory, modernity allows for
democracy, freedom (albeit one controlled by social responsibility and
spiritual welfare), justice and peaceful interaction between different peoples,
thus promoting the creation of a truly global community, which, El-Affendi
says, is in accordance with Islamic teachings. In this regard, Islam, properly
understood, can play an important role as a source of moral guidance to create
a peaceful and just world order and to end the present heavily-skewed global
imbalances of power and resources. El-Affendi sees this as part of the mandate
of a community that regards itself as a ‘witness over mankind’, which should
manifest itself in transcending self-interest in favour of global
responsibility, attacking consumerism, nurturing the environment and offering
an alternative to the international order based on the notion of the egotistic
nation-state as a collection of individuals and groups motivated largely by
narrowly-defined self-interest. These notions should, he argues, be recast in a
moral context by redefining the role of the Muslim ummah as the conscience of
mankind. One of El-Affendi’s serious concerns with
traditional as well as contemporary Muslim political thought is that it does
not adequately provide for formal decision-making mechanisms suitable for a
complex, modern state. One reason for this is that both are based on the model
of the small-scale and closely-knit polity established by the Prophet in
Medina, which, in turn, was built on a society characterized by mutual trust,
close personal interaction and easy, mainly face-to-face communications. The
charismatic nature of the leadership provided by the Prophet made it
unnecessary to have formal decision-making structures that would require all
leading figures to take part in the political process. Today, however,
El-Affendi notes, the situation is vastly different, and more institutionalized
and formal arrangements for decision-making and power-sharing are required in
order to administer large nation-states. This is something that Muslim political
thought has not devoted sufficient attention to. In this context, El-Affendi
argues that that the idea of a single Caliph, so central to traditional Sunni
political thought, may have to be replaced in favour of rule by a council of
people, a system more in tune with the concept and realities of the modern
state. El-Affendi is also critical of the Islamists’
tendency to hanker after a single saintly hero, in the model of an ideal Caliph
or a Mujaddid or a Mahdi, who could, almost miraculously, solve all the
problems of the Muslims in particular, and the world in general. He rightly
regards this as misplaced utopianism, pointing out the impossibility of
applying political techniques suitable for small city states to vast countries.
The classical Sunni caliphate model that both traditional ulema and Islamists
seek to recreate, he insists, belongs to the category of republican city-states
of the past and is unworkable in today, in a world of vast, multi-ethnic,
modern states. An aspect of the political practice of many
contemporary Islamist groups that engages El-Affendi’s concern is what he
regards as their overwhelming focus on the fight against foreign enemies,
whether real or imaginary, which has been at the cost of the struggle for
internal reforms within the Muslim community. This indicates a lack of
sufficient introspection and self-critique and an unfortunate tendency to blame
others wholly for one’s own weaknesses, failures and travails. Because of this,
he argues, all sorts of corruption, despotism, mismanagement and ineptitude
have been tolerated among Muslims ‘in the name of the fight against this enemy
or that’, while ‘the enemy within, the biggest of all, was left untouched’. A key aspect of the practice of modern Islamist
movements that El-Affendi finds greatly problematic is their near obsession
with ruling through restriction, control and punishment, rather than through
working for the positive enablement of their citizens. This has made for
proto-fascist tendencies to emerge within their ranks, ultimately causing the
very people whom they supposedly wanted to reform in the name of Islam to
oppose and even, as in some places, revolt against them. This, so El-Affendi
says, was not the original Islamic idea of a political community, and can only
be counterproductive to the cause of building up a truly moral Islamic society
and polity. By seeking to ‘establish’ Islam through coercion,
and thus making capture of the state and its coercive powers their first or
major concern, Islamist forces might thus only be causing their own downfall,
El-Affendi argues. Their harsh, authoritarian approach to enforcing Islamic
morality can only lead to corruption and widespread hypocrisy, causing
alienation from, rather than genuine commitment to, Islam. This means, El-Affendi writes, that the search for
an ideal state must begin with the search for freedom for Muslims, including
the freedom to think, to act, to even sin and to repent, to find oneself and
one’s fulfillment in obeying God—only then can a truly righteous Muslim
community and state emerge. This requires that, for the present, Muslims must
participate wholeheartedly in the struggle for democracy, for right of every
individual not to be coerced into doing anything his or her will. Only in this
freedom will society be able to evolve an ethics based on the Prophetic model,
wherein people submit to Islam voluntarily and abide by its rules by their
conscience, not through fear of the state and its agencies of punishment. At
the same time, El-Affendi adds, the freedom that he advocates is not one
without moral restraints. To be free is not to be amoral. Rather, it means to
be free from external, undesirable constraints. Yet, to be genuinely free also
requires that the state must not be totalitarian, contrary to how several
modern Islamist ideologues have conceived of it. The ideal Muslim state, as
well as the Muslim community in general, does have the duty to help each
individual achieve his or her moral potential, but it cannot shoulder the
individual’s ultimate duty with regard to his or her own actions. El-Affendi
recognizes that for any political community to function there has to be an
element of coercion involved, but, he says, the ideal polity cannot approve of
any element of coercion other than the minimum inherent in the principle of
community itself. The Muslim state or the Muslim community cannot compel people
to be righteous against their will, for that would only lead to hypocrisy,
which Islam abhors. This is also a sure recipe for despotism, as the state, imagining
itself to be the instrument of the Divine Will, can easily assume its moral
duty to be to compel people to act against their own conscience. In other
words, then, the state must be a democratic one, based on the free will of its
citizens and the principle of peaceful resolution of differences and free
debate about the demands of Islam and the operation of the community. It should
also respect cultural and religious pluralism, and accommodate non-Muslims as
equal citizens with equal rights and freedom. El-Affendi argues the case for a
polity in a plural society as being an association of independent religious
communities coexisting with each other, governed by a treaty rather than by a
rigid Constitution in order to give the communities greater autonomy. Such a
treaty would detail the rights and duties of all communities and would
safeguard their common existence, similar to covenant of Medina covenant that
brought the Muslims, under the Prophet, with the non-Muslim communities of
Medina, in a common polity. This would be a different sort of polity to the
conventional modern state. Communities would join together not as subjects of
an all powerful state, but as members of communities united voluntarily, each
pursuing its own way of life in full freedom. This polity would allow for only
that much coercion as is needed to safeguard and maintain the polity itself,
but coercion would not the basis of the polity. In such a polity, a person
would be free to join the community and polity of his or her choice or leave
freely, something that is absent in the current international order, where
citizens must conform to state-dictated norms and where freedom of movement to
join other polities is severely restricted. In place of the territory-based
modern state, El-Affendi suggests a polity which is not strictly territorial,
and an international order based on peacefully co-existing communities rather
than territorially-based and mutually exclusive nation states. It would not be
an intrusive, coercive organisation that seeks to impose specific norms.
Instead, it would be a co-operative association to help people to live freely
according to the dictates of their conscience. It would conform to the shariah,
but the shariah would not be imposed. Rather, the conformity to the shariah
would be to the extent of the free expression of the free will of its Muslim
citizens. Such a state is to be distinguished from
conventional states in that it has a higher moral purpose. It should,
El-Affendi says, serve as a light for all humankind, and not being engrossed,
as all other states are, in an endless search for comforts and material goods
for its people. It must be characterized by a philosophy of giving and sharing,
unlike conventional states, whose component groups vie with each other for the
maximum possible self-aggrandisement. This brings El-Affendi to the greatly controversial
issue of the imposition of the shariah. He persuasively argues that attempts to
force Muslims to abide by the shariah have inevitably failed in the past, and
have even proven counter-productive. In this regard, then, conventional
Islamist political thought is gravely lacking. The shariah, El-Affendi says,
can rule only through the willing consensus of Muslims, when the community
observing it perceives it as a liberating act, as the true fulfillment of the
self. In other words, since the shariah must entail willing compliance to its
rules, in actual fact it can never be imposed, whether by the state, an
Islamist party or by Muslim clerics. When it is imposed against the will of the
people, it is no longer shariah. When only coercion, not consent, underpins the
rule of the shariah, it becomes hypocrisy. The issue of the enforcement of the shariah by the
state also shapes the way in which Islamists conceive the state itself—as
almost an end in itself, or, at least, as the principle means to enforce the
shariah. El-Affendi points out that this displaces the role of individuals in
establishing justice, making social activity, including the dispensation of justice,
dependent on the will of rulers, who can thereby easily turn into despots.
Islamists often take the state as end in itself. And, since the Islamist party
or the ‘Islamic’ state comes to be seen as an end in itself, in many cases
self-styled Islamic movements have exhibited an unfortunate tendency of
allowing their ends to govern their means, not stopping from engaging in
blatantly un-Islamic and criminal acts, such as killing innocent people and
engaging in terrorism, in order to achieve what they regard as noble ends.
El-Affendi insists that Islam does not allow for this sort of approach at all. El-Affendi is particularly critical of modern
Islamist ideologues, such as the Egyptian Syed Qutb and the Pakistani Abul Ala
Maududi, who conceived of an ideal Islamic state as being totalitarian,
anti-democratic, authoritarian and coercive. He is bitter about what he calls
the Islamists’ ‘self-righteous pretensions’, which translates into ‘a readiness
to resort to violence at the slightest pretext’. He likens them to the Khawarij
or Kharijites, an early splinter group from among the Muslims, who saw
themselves alone as true Muslims, and the rest of the world, including other
Muslims, as deviant, aberrant, even anti-Islamic, thus ruling out any room for
compromise. While still upholding the notion of a Muslim state
moulded or guided by religio-moral concerns and principles, el-Affendi points
to the serious gaps in modern Islamist political thought, indicating the way
forward for the emergence of a genuinely democratic, pluralist and
contextually-relevant Muslim political discourse. Yoginder Sikand works with the Centre for the Study
of Social Exclusion and Inclusive Social Policy at the National Law School,
Bangalore . http://www.countercurrents.org/sikand150709.htm |
Please report any
broken links to
Webmaster
Copyright © 1988-2012 irfi.org. All Rights Reserved.
Disclaimer